decides to test ALZ-112 on his father, after his research program at Gen-Sys has been shut down (having in the meantime inadvertently caused permanent enhancements in Caesar). We can look at this decision from the starting assumptions of three standard ethical theories: consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics, working our way from those assumptions through the ethical consequences that follow from them.
Consequentialist ethics begins with the assumption thatâas the name clearly hints atâwhat matters in moral decisionmaking is the consequences of oneâs action. Nineteenth-century philosopher John Stuart Mill is one of the most influential consequentialists, and for him a good action has the consequence of increasing overall happiness, while a bad action has the consequence of increasing overall pain. So, for Mill it does not really matter what Willâs intentions were (they were good, we assume, as he was both concerned with his fatherâs health and with a potential cure for Alzheimerâs for all humankind), what matters is what happened as a result of his action. And what happened was a disaster. Not only did his father actually die of the disease, but Willâs attempt to solve the problem that led tothe failure of his cure will eventually condemn the human race to extinction. Thatâs as bad as consequences can possibly be, Iâd say. There is a caveat, however. If the totality of chimp happiness outweighs the pain caused by humanityâs extinction, Will may still be vindicated on consequentialist grounds. That, unfortunately, isnât going to help Will or anyone he cared for, except perhaps Caesar.
Deontological ethics is the idea that there are universal rules of conduct that govern our ethical judgments. Religious commandments are an example of a deontological moral system. The most important secular approach to deontology is the one devised by Immanuel Kant in the eighteenth century, and is based on his idea that there is only one fundamental moral rule, which he called the categorical imperative (itâs not only an imperative, but no exceptions are allowed!). In one version, the imperative essentially says that we ought to treat other people never solely as means to an end, but always as ends in themselves. In other words, we must respect their integrity as moral agents distinct from but equal to ourselves.
Itâs not exactly clear how Kant would evaluate Willâs actions towards his father. On the one hand, Will attempted the cure on his father because he was genuinely worried about the latterâs health, so Will clearly valued his father as an individual for his own sake. On the other hand, if part of Willâs goal was to find a general cure for Alzheimerâs, then by using his father as an experimental subject, he was using him as a means toward a further end. Moreover, he did so without obtaining his fatherâs explicit consentâindeed, he never even attempted to inform his father about the treatment before or after it was administered. For a deontologist, the consequences arenât what determine the rightness or wrongness of an action at all, so even if Will had succeeded in liberating humanity from Alzheimerâs (instead of starting a chain of events that eventually leads to the extinction of the entire species), he would still have done the wrong thing. You can see why Kant was well known for being a bit too strict of a moralist.
Finally, we get to virtue ethics, an idea that was common in ancient Greece and was elaborated in particular by Aristotle. Virtue ethicists are not really concerned with determining whatâs right or wrong, but rather with what kind of life one ought to live in order to flourish. This means that Aristotlewould consider neither the consequences of an action per se, nor necessarily the intentions of the moral agent, but would look instead at whether the action was the reflection of a âvirtuousâ
Aziz Ansari, Eric Klinenberg
Derek Catron
Eliza Gayle
Kris Cook
D. Harrison Schleicher
Shadonna Richards
Laura Matthews
Nicole Thorn
Grace Lumpkin
Lexi Connor